I started writing my third post
for this blog but it ended up becoming a draft paper on my philosophical
methodology1 so there’s been a gap of time since my last blog post.
(I’ve also accidentally been on
Pacific Time apparently, according to my blog settings, so my times are wrong
but I’ve corrected it for this post.)
Here I want to carry on from a
fuller version of the last quote, which I cite in that draft paper, namely:
‘There is a sense of community
among contributors to these debates, however overtly critical analytic
philosophers can seem of each other’s work. Progress comes through criticism,
often in the form of unexpected counterexamples to general theses. Jenefer Robinson’s
paper on “Expression and Arousal of Emotion in Music” (Part XI) nicely
illustrates how a debate advances. She enters into a dialogue with other
contributors and defines her own position in relation to theirs. This is the
familiar analytic mode. The cumulative effect of such debates is a sense of
concentrated effort on carefully circumscribed ground”2
I like the way Lamarque and Olsen
have chosen a female philosopher as an example of someone who successfully demonstrates
how analytic philosophy goes about constructive debate. This, I think, helps
bust the myth that women are not naturally suited to debates structured around
counter-argument. Surely, to assume that this style of argumentation requires
male traits is, in itself, a sexist assumption? Attributing aggressive, antagonistic
and adversarial intentions to the analytic approach to philosophy is unfounded
and misleading. If philosophy is conducted as a general humanities style discussion,
then philosophy loses its distinctive flavour and contribution as a discipline.
It makes it indistinguishable from intellectual history which effectively merely
states and reproduces what people have thought down the ages. This eradicates
the valuable tools of philosophy which uses logic and features of scientific
discourse to dissect, investigate, evaluate and critically assess arguments in
philosophy/philosophical texts to arrive at the truth and to engage in
independent thinking. It also begs the question which ideas, which groups of
people are these historians picking out. This makes it just as susceptible to being
influenced by bias and ideology as any other subject. The History of Ideas must
not be confused with the History of Philosophy. The latter focuses on
philosophy whereas the former is rooted in history. Analytic philosophy also helps
us to understand the approach of philosophers of the so-called long early
modern period which is roughly from the seventeenth century through to the mid-nineteenth
century. As Scruton sums up Spinoza’s attitude:
“Spinoza would have condemned the
practice (known nowadays as the ‘history of ideas’) whereby a study of the ancestry
of ideas takes precedence over an enquiry into their truth and meaning.”3
Hence, when I go about
researching a philosopher I have my analytic philosophy hat on. I don’t read
the texts of eg Spinoza as though they are a novel to be discussed or a history
book containing factual information which may or may not be disputed as to its
accuracy. I read Spinoza to understand his philosophical arguments and where
his independent thinking took him. I go on a journey with him in a way that
does not superimpose my own modern perspectives. Nor do I wish to ‘box him in’
into a confined, narrow cultural, time-ridden space because he wished to
transcend thought-time. He saw Judaism as not confined by certain present day
strictures of his era but as a religion open to independent thought and
discourse while keeping its fundamental religious principles. I think Spinoza
was able to keep things like this in tension without confusion. Maybe this is a
situation that is often experienced by those reading Spinoza, that what appears
to many as a contradiction, for Spinoza, is not.
So, I strive to strike a balance
between appreciating philosophical arguments in themselves while bearing in
mind Walton’s comment4 which I cross-apply to the History of
Philosophy, that ‘It cannot be
correct… to perceive a work in categories which are totally foreign to the artist
and his society…’, or as in this case, foreign to the philosopher and his
environment.
1You can read it on my academia page at: https://www.academia.edu/33536608/Spinoza_Paper_on_Methodology_2017_draft_
2Lamarque, Olsen (ed) (2004), General
Introduction to “Aesthetics and the
Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition: An Anthology” edited by Lamarque
and Olsen, Blackwell Publishing p5
3Scruton, R., (1986) “Spinoza”, Past Masters Oxford University Press p21
4Walton, K., “Categories
of Art” in “Aesthetics and the
Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition: An Anthology” (2004), edited by
Lamarque and Olsen, Blackwell Publishing p154
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.