Chapter 8: Feminist
Interpretation of Spinoza On Oppression
Following on from my previous
chapter, I shall expand on the theme of oppression and rights. In chapter 7, I
gave a textual analysis of chapter 1 section 5 (TP)[i]
of Spinoza’s arguments in the original Latin. Here, I wish to take the same
section but this time I shall attempt to illustrate how Spinoza’s political
philosophy in his TP can inform feminism, feminist philosophy and jurisprudence
because oppression is a key issue in these research areas. In so doing, I will
also show the relevance of Spinoza’s philosophy to feminism today because, I
maintain, Spinoza’s arguments can cross-apply to contemporary feminism and
feminist jurisprudence, even in passages where he is not directly addressing
women’s social situation. By testing Spinoza’s notions on feminist accounts, I
will demonstrate the strength and truth of his arguments through suggesting
ways Spinozianism can resolve logical tensions between them. Moreover, I hope
to make evident the practical relevance and possible application of Spinoza’s
concepts, thus establishing a further dimension to the analytic-feminist strand
of my interpretation of Spinoza. I also suggest two claims: One, that Spinoza’s
principle of defending rights for all in his TP gives philosophical
underpinning and support to the aims of intersectional feminism. Two, that Spinoza’s
philosophy can motivate the normative claim that intersectional feminism must
strive to go further than simply being inclusive, it must embrace a broad
definition of woman and treat all women as equals. Each intersectional feminist
should, by definition, fight for and uphold all women’s rights as strongly as
she does for the rights that are relevant to her life and identities.
Indeed, it is evident that, if
women’s rights were fought for and upheld by everyone in society, rather than
leaving it up to feminist movements to fight for, secure and maintain, as is
often the case, then there would be more justice in society, be it ethical,
social, political or legal. This Spinozian principle of upholding the rights of
all, I maintain, highlights the need to encompass all of humanity into the
concept of human rights, applying rights to both men and women without sex
discrimination, as well as applying it to intersex and those who identify as
non-binary and trans. It encompasses rights “irrespective of race, age, sexual
orientation, ability or class”[ii]
or marital status. I would also add religion (including women in religious institutions,
for example, convents, cloistered or not, who are often forgotten, so can, as a result, be even more vulnerable). Rights for all also extends meaningfully into
intersectional feminism and feminist philosophy of law and jurisprudence to
avoid falling into “‘essentialism’ or ‘ethnocentricism’” in feminism whereby
the female experience is sometimes erroneously reduced to one stereotype, often
a white, cis, heterosexual female rather than reflecting all women[iii].
This was a criticism famously elaborated by Audrey Lorde, who, as a “black,
lesbian feminist socialist writer”[iv],
noticed that descriptions of the so-called female experience were failing to be
inclusive enough of women of various identities. Nevertheless, Leslie Bender
puts less emphasis on this concern, because she feels there is a great deal to
be gained from examining “common experiences and patterns that emerge from
shared tellings of life events”[v].
The potential value of this approach is: “What were experienced as personal
hurts individually suffered reveal themselves as a collective experience of
oppression”[vi].
Indeed, there is empirical evidence of patriarchal oppression being a
sociological phenomenon which forms a global pattern. This pattern extends to
trans women who, once they are perceived or identified as female, begin to
suffer the same distinctive forms of female sexual harassment, abuse and
violence, including fatalities. All this, I think, provides empirical grounds
to argue that the existence of a diverse and completely inclusive sisterhood is
not a myth, but is in fact a reality.
Both Bender and Lorde make
important points but there remains a logical tension between their two
approaches which needs resolving to reflect such empirical evidence of patterns
of female oppression (very often involving various forms of economic
oppression) across all continents, societies, cultures, traditions, religions,
and identities. Should feminism examine women’s experiences through identity
differences (a Lorde-like approach)? Or through finding a general umbrella of
common ground between all women (a Bender-like approach)? Is it possible to
balance the advantages of embracing all women’s identities explicitly (as
opposed to making implicit assumptions) without losing a sense of the
sisterhood? A concept Lorde questions as potentially being “a pretence of
homogeneity of experience”[vii].
I wish to resolve this logical tension
in a way which goes further than the answer of intersectional feminism by
drawing on Spinoza’s political and ethical principle of actively defending and
upholding others’ rights as one’s own throughout one’s lifetime. In this way, I
attempt to show how Spinoza has the philosophical concepts to fill a possible
theoretical gap in intersectional feminism.
I think intersectional feminism can
successfully address the error of universalising one concept of ‘woman’ at the
expense of including women of all identities and by acknowledging how their
additional identities impact on their experience of being a woman. I think its
long-term key to success is to be actively inclusive of all of the parallel
identities women have (not prioritising some over others) as well as being
fully inclusive of all gender identities (intersex who self-identify as female;
transwomen (and possibly transmen and transboys); non-binary women, for example, agender
women; gender fluid women (gender identity changes over time); multigender
women. However, what I think intersectionality possibly struggles to address,
is the accompanying concept and ethos of the sisterhood, defined as “a strong
feeling of friendship and support among women who are involved in action to
improve women's rights”[viii].
This would be akin to Spinoza’s
principle of love thy neighbour which he thought all religions could adopt and
relate to one another in accordance with it. Thus, it is a principle, if taken
in Spinoza’s sense of it, which is inclusive of all religious beliefs. In
Spinoza’s era, society was religion-based and non-belief or atheism was often
outlawed. A present day application of this principle can be adapted to suit
modern and global society which includes a greater variety of belief systems
and none. Therefore, I think a contemporary application of his principle to a
feminist concept of a sisterhood would run along the same lines.
However, it is one thing merely to aim at non-discrimination by ensuring feminism does not implicitly
perpetuate forms of oppression itself by excluding and silencing sections of
the female population. It is quite another to truly perceive and accept all
women (especially those who are conscious of women’s oppression and act to
improve women’s rights) as your equal and fight for their women’s rights just
as you would your own. I think intersectional feminism is the best placed to attempt
to resolve the former, that is, the internal discrimination/oppression problem.
Their aim of inclusivity has addressed past issues of, for instance, the
silencing and exclusion of lesbians and black feminists from attending or
participating actively and socially within feminist groups. Such problems were
highlighted by radical lesbian feminists who protested the exclusion of
lesbians and lesbian issues from the Second Congress to Unite Women in the USA
in 1970. Bell Hook famously raised awareness of how racial and class oppression
intersects with women’s oppression and feminism in her seminal book ‘Ain't I a
Woman?: Black women and feminism’[ix].
However, I maintain that it remains unclear to what extent intersectional
feminism resolves the second tension, namely, how an intersectional sisterhood is
created and maintained. Although it is beneficial to have both a variety of
feminist schools of thought as well as feminist sub-groups where women who
share the same identities as each other can share and address the additional
patterns of oppression they suffer, this can sometimes result in a lack of
cohesion and sense of sisterhood within the general umbrella of feminism.
Nevertheless, there are campaigns
such as One Billion Rising, a global campaign against reproductive and sexual
oppression, abuse and violence against all women, including “cisgender,
transgender, and those who hold fluid identities that are subject to
gender-based violence” and LGBTQIA+ communities[x].
Within this campaign, one can see Spinoza’s concepts in practice.
Firstly, that oppression and
violence deprive one of independence:
“each is so long independent, as he can guard
against oppression by another”[xi]
(TP, chapter 2, section 15)
“everyone is … so far independent, as he is able to repel all violence”[xii]
(TP, chapter 2 section 9)
The links between oppression,
violence and women’s levels of independence can be seen in the One Billion
Rising campaign which seeks to empower women by freeing them to reach a greater
level of independence through knowing their rights and powers, which help them
overcome past, current and possibly even future oppression and violence. It is
specifically aimed at the oppression of women and girls by men and tracking
these patterns of women’s oppression across a wide range of “systemic violence in
economic, political, socio-cultural, environmental and ideological spheres”[xiii].
This can be seen in their 2019 manifesto which focuses on ending: “Rape,
Battery, Incest, Sexual Harassment, Female Genital Mutilation (FGM), Sexual
Slavery and Trafficking, Child Marriage, Femicide, Sexual, Gender and
Reproductive Oppression, Violence Towards LGBTQIA+ Communities, Toxic
Masculinity, Poverty/ Economic Injustice/ Labor Exploitation, Climate
Destruction and Environmental Plunder, Racism, Hate and Discrimination,
Religious Fundamentalism, State and Institutional Violence/ Militarization/
War, Forced Displacement/ Immigrant and Migrant Abuse.” [xiv]
This list illustrates the extent of women’s oppression globally across every
aspect and area of life within this patriarchal world we live in. The Youth
section of the movement goes even further by including university campuses, slut
shaming, bullying and sexism, misogyny, demanding women’s access to open spaces
without fear, the right to education (throughout school and higher education to
PhD), objectification and stereotyping of women and girls and domestic
violence, and many more issues[xv].
Secondly, One Billion Rising
provides empirical support for the possibility of and necessity for a diverse
and inclusive sisterhood within which all women fight alongside each other for
women’s rights for all women. (Men can support the cause by joining the Men
Rising campaign which supports ending oppression of all women and girls[xvi].)
The main aim of a sisterhood is to redress the gender injustice in patriarchal
society. In this way, it fulfils Spinoza’s requirement of love thy neighbour,
which in practice means justice for all[xvii].
Transposed into present day feminism, this requirement specifies that there
should be justice for people of all sex and gender identities, rather than a
bias in favour of the archetypal “reasonable man”[xviii]
who is modelled on the (cis white heterosexual) male sex, while claiming to
represent all.
A more detailed description of
Spinoza’s argument is perhaps that people should align their (positive)
passions with the double-meaning principle of love thy neighbour/defend and
uphold their rights as your own[xix].
The rationale of this principle should also prevail over the (negative) passions.
If this principle were applied to the law courts, as Spinoza suggests[xx],
then I think that discrimination on the basis of sex (biological sex or sex
identity) would be eradicated. It would potentially bring about true rights for
all because men would not lose any rights, but, unlike the current global
situation, women’s rights would be recognised and upheld to the same level as
men’s rights. As the principle states for all, this would hold true, regardless
of the person’s gender identity as well as other identities, such as racial and
sexual orientation. Given Spinoza’s arguments for religious toleration in his
TTP, this would also guard against discrimination on the basis of religious
affiliation. This, I maintain, provides a theoretical and practical framework
which can both strengthen the current legal ideal of non-discrimination and
gender neutrality but actively address the shortcomings of the legal system of
upholding its ideal. Spinoza’s principle of upholding and defending rights for
all just as (passionately) as you do your own, if applied consistently,
addresses the concerns of all three main contemporary feminist movements:
First wave feminism sees the
social and legal gender problem as being caused by a “male monopoly of law”
which introduces “inequalities” into an otherwise objective, fair system[xxi].
“For second phase feminists, of
differing political persuasions, the root problem with law lies in its
pretended impartiality, objectivity and rationality.”[xxii]
Third wave feminism puts legal
gender inequality down to hidden gender biases meaning that although the “law
is gendered”, this is compounded by inconsistencies in application which make
it difficult to track gender discrimination[xxiii].
Spinoza, I suggest, gives us a
way of transcending all three explanations, because, no matter which account of
the root cause holds true, in all three explanations, it holds true that
women’s rights are not upheld and defended to the same degree and to the same
extent as men’s rights, across all other identities, such as race, class, age. Thus,
regardless of different identities between women, they share a common form of
oppression, namely, gender oppression. I refer to it as gender oppression
rather than sex oppression because it not only relates to being biologically
female, but also extends into gender identity, such as transwomen. Transwomen
suffer an alarmingly high rate of violence, often fatal, once they identify as,
or are perceived as female by men.
Hence, Spinoza resolves the
logical tension between Lorde and Bender’s statements[xxiv]
by homing in on two approaches to the problem. One, by arguing that the
principle of justice for all must be consistently applied in society throughout
people’s lifetime, by individuals and justice systems, not just as an ideal but
in practice. The (negative) passions must not be allowed to introduce bias and
injustice, whether it be on a personal, legal or political level. Two, by
explicitly writing about oppression, Spinoza is fulfilling the general
political criteria that: “..in order to advance any political movement, there
exists the need to raise the consciousness of those being oppressed.”[xxv]
Furthermore, Spinoza’s philosophy answers the feminist call for raising
awareness and increasing knowledge of oppression: “By identifying sites
of…oppression, feminist scholars….demonstrated further the supremacy which men
have traditionally assumed and maintained in society”[xxvi]
and still do. As I discussed in chapter 6, Spinoza shows awareness of
gender oppression in the private sphere, when he argues against the role of the
patriarchal, head of the household who treats his family as his property. This
is an impressive argument for a man living in the 17th century,
given that feminists today are still having to refute gender biased notions of
a woman’s appropriate role in the home that are often based on the same
Aristotelian-style idea of gendered, binary biological limitations that
Spinoza, back then, rejected. Moreover, Spinoza’s philosophy also maintains
that everyone has the same nature, thus he is not suggesting a binary or
gendered concept of women and men’s nature. He also has a positive concept of
nature and God’s relation to it.
In contrast, Oldenburg introduced
the notion of a “Masculine Philosophy” as an “explicit goal” of the Royal
Society[xxvii].
Many male natural philosophers/scientists, such as Boyle, Bacon and Descartes,
reinforced the misogyny behind this new approach to natural and scientific
research with their gendered language[xxviii].
Science and philosophy (since there was less distinction between the two fields
in that era) were to go from being “passive and weak” “female” disciplines to
being “active” male disciplines [xxix].
They looked upon women as being analogous to the natural world and thought both
should be effectively tamed and oppressed by men. Nature was referred to using feminine
pronouns and Bacon encouraged men to “capture” and “hound her”, “bind her to
[mans] service and make her [man’s] slave”[xxx].
Descartes advocated mastering and possessing nature while Boyle went so far as
to claim that men should “bring nature to be serviceable to [men’s] particular
ends, whether of health, or riches, or sensual delight”[xxxi].
The result of such attitudes in
the Royal Society and among male scientists (who were also becoming reviewers once
Oldenburg began the peer review system) in that era lead to a rise in sexism
against women scientists which still lingers on today[xxxii].
One aspect of this sexism in STEM
is turning so-called “norms of masculine behavior” into “norms of scientific
behavior” and “method”[xxxiii].
These norms, which are claimed to be contradictory to “norms of feminine
behavior” include learning to be “objective, impartial, logical, unemotional,
disinterested, and independent”[xxxiv].
However, as one sees in Spinoza’s arguments for independence, this is part of
living a good human life, free from various forms of oppression. Consequently,
by labelling independence a male trait, I argue that patriarchy is
fundamentally oppressing women and restricting their capacity to be free and
reach their full potential. Moreover, I think this constitutes good grounds for
encouraging women to be independent researchers in their chosen discipline, to
free them from biased patriarchal systems and institutions as well as to show
that women are not, by nature, unsuited to independent thinking, researching or
living. Otherwise, the sexist stereotype persists that women are only suited to
being dependent, such as seeking help from others or collaborating with others,
which simply is not the case.
Furthermore, as can be seen with
women philosophers such as Lady Mary Shepherd (18th-19th
century), women are perfectly capable and well-suited to excelling in
“objective, impartial, logical”[xxxv]
thought, amongst other things, so this gender bias about their cognitive abilities
must not be used to make women lack confidence in subjects which require these
attributes. I would not advocate removing these qualities from being valued in
research, on the basis that they are male qualities, because I reject the
notion that they are inherently male qualities, they are merely qualities that
can be learnt by all, whether the person identifies as male, female or
non-binary. The focus for progress in science, philosophy and other disciplines
should, instead, be on removing gendered language, notions (including what
constitutes male and female traits so both these and gender neutral traits can
be valued), stereotypes and bias so everyone can reach their full potential.
Behavioural stereotypes also mean
that “Western scientists are expected to be aggressive and competitive, and
jeopardize their careers when they do not exhibit these traits”[xxxvi],
which puts women scientists and women philosophers (and women in other careers
where these traits are needed to progress) at a disadvantage. By penalising
women for displaying (or criticising them for allegedly possessing or
displaying) aggression or competitiveness, women are substantially held back in
their careers from this attitude alone. Such disadvantages are also in addition
to other biases they suffer, such as not being perceived as specialists or
knowledgeable, experiencing gendered harassment, unjustifiable pay gaps and so
on. Meanwhile, the same behaviour is normalised or rewarded when exhibited by
men, giving them a head start and psychological advantages, such as, being
labelled and perceived as more independent, intelligent, impartial, expert and
logical.
A second aspect of sexism in
STEM, philosophy and academia in general, is that barriers faced by women are
far more extensive than just the original patriarchal ideology of oppressing
women and nature expressed by Oldenburg, Boyle, Bacon and others. (Although not
so by Spinoza.) It became a pattern of oppression of women which impacted on their
“access to universities” (including appallingly “restrictive admissions”), and
then only offering them “menial research roles”, “less financial assistance” on
top of “exclusion” from, for instance, “meetings and collaborations and
information networks”[xxxvii].
All of which reinforced and compounded the limiting, gendered behavioural norms
aforementioned.
Spinoza, however, in chapter 1,
section 5 of his TP, I think, is showing awareness of widespread oppression in
the public sphere, including the legal world of the law courts. Given that
Spinoza saw how gendered the law is through his legal battle with his sister
over their inheritance and yet, rather than use his male privilege against her,
he gave her more than she was legally entitled to receive, I suggest Spinoza’s
discussion of oppression in the public and legal sphere in section 5,
implicitly includes women’s oppression. Likewise, Spinoza’s natural philosophy
and metaphysics (amongst other branches of philosophy he engages in) are not
imbued with elements of the 17th century Royal Society’s sexism. As
I have argued in this volume, Spinoza’s politics is not advocating misogyny and
to claim otherwise, I have suggested, is a misreading of his original Latin
texts. Additionally, I do not agree with Barbone and Rice’s claim that
Spinoza’s political philosophy possibly forgets about rights for social groups
(“such as ‘women’s rights’, ‘gay rights’, etc.”) by referring to individuals in
his “conception of right”[xxxviii].
I think there is textual evidence to the contrary. It is apparent that Spinoza
accounts for different religious groups and people of various cultural
identities and norms living alongside each other, especially in his TTP.
Hence, as I have argued,
Spinoza’s philosophy is well-suited to the development of feminist concepts and
arguments, such as the ones I have offered in this chapter. When Spinoza does
address sexist systems or concepts in society, he does not argue for creating
masculine societal norms, as Bacon and Boyle advocated. Spinoza’s arguments, I
think, can help resolve the tensions within the concept of a sisterhood. Both
conceptually and in practice, the same principle of rights for all must still
apply between all members of the sisterhood who identify as women (including
transwomen and intersex who identify as women). Each member of the sisterhood
must, therefore, defend and uphold the rights of all women, of all identities
and cultures, across the world, including indigenous women. As a result, by
creating a sisterhood based on diversity of experience, we both retain
intersectionality while gaining an understanding of the distinctively female
“collective experience of oppression” that Bender suggests[xxxix],
but in all its various forms, giving a richer picture of the female condition.
In this way, Spinoza’s philosophy of justice, (amongst other features of his
philosophy) I think, is not only relevant to political, social and moral
philosophy, but can also be a source of inspiration for feminist philosophy.
[i] Benedict de Spinoza, Benedicti de Spinoza
Opera quotquot reperta sunt, ed. J. van Vloten and JPN Land, Editio Altera,
Tomus Primus (Netherlands: Hagae comitum, M. Nijhoff, 1895), 270–71,
https://archive.org/details/Spinoza1895Opera2VlotenLand2ed/page/n7.
[ii] Hilaire Barnett, Introduction to
Feminist Jurisprudence, 1st edition (London: Cavendish Publ, 1998), 20.
[iii] Barnett, 20.
[iv] Barnett, 20.
[v] Barnett, 20.
[vi] Barnett, 20.
[vii] Barnett, 20.
[viii]
N/A, ‘Sisterhood’, in Cambridge
Dictionary (UK: Cambridge University Press, N/A),
https://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/english/sisterhood.
[ix] bell hooks, Ain’t I a Woman: Black
Women and Feminism, Nachdr., Pluto Classics (London: Pluto Press, 2001).
[x] N/A, ‘The 2019 Campaign RISING: FROM A CAMPAIGN, TO A WAY OF LIFE’,
Campaign; educational, One Billion Rising, 2019,
https://www.onebillionrising.org/about/campaign/.
[xi] Benedict de Spinoza, THE CHIEF WORKS
of BENEDICT DE SPINOZA, trans. R. H. M. Elwes, REVISED EDITION. London, UK,
vol. I, BOHN’S PHILOSOPHICAL LIBRARY. SPINOZA’S WORKS. (London: york street,
covent garden: GEORGE BELL & SONS, 1891), 296, http://lf-oll.s3.amazonaws.com/titles/1710/1321.01_Bk.pdf.
[xii] Spinoza, I:295.
[xiii]
N/A, ‘The 2019 Campaign RISING: FROM A CAMPAIGN, TO A WAY OF LIFE’.
[xiv] N/A.
[xv] N/A, ‘Youth Rising’, Campaign;
educational, One Billion Rising, 2019,
https://www.onebillionrising.org/resources/youth-rising/.
[xvi] N/A, ‘Men Rising’, Campaign; educational,
One Billion Rising, 2019,
https://www.onebillionrising.org/resources/men-rising/.
[xvii]
Spinoza, Benedicti de Spinoza Opera
quotquot reperta sunt, 270–71.
[xviii]
Barnett, Introduction to Feminist
Jurisprudence, 6.
[xix] Spinoza, Benedicti de Spinoza Opera
quotquot reperta sunt, 270–71.
[xx] Spinoza, 270–71.
[xxi] Barnett, Introduction to Feminist
Jurisprudence, 5.
[xxii]
Barnett, 6.
[xxiii]
Barnett, 7.
[xxiv]
Barnett, 20.
[xxv] Barnett, 12.
[xxvi]
Barnett, 4.
[xxvii]
Janet A. Kourany, ‘Philosophy of Science:
A New Program for Philosophy of Science, in Many Voices’, in Philosophy in a
Feminist Voice: Critiques and Reconstructions, ed. Janet A. Kourany
(Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press, 1998), 231.
[xxviii]
Kourany, 231–32.
[xxix]
Kourany, 231.
[xxx] Kourany, 231.
[xxxi]
Kourany, 231–32.
[xxxii]
Kourany, 232.
[xxxiii]
Kourany, 232.
[xxxiv]
Kourany, 232.
[xxxv]
Kourany, 232.
[xxxvi]
Kourany, 232.
[xxxvii]
Kourany, 232–33.
[xxxviii]
Benedictus de Spinoza, ‘Introduction’, in
Political Treatise, trans. Samuel Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett Pub,
2000), 18, footnote 61.
[xxxix]
Barnett, Introduction to Feminist
Jurisprudence, 20.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.