Wednesday, 10 January 2018

Spinoza vol 1 ebook Chapter 10: The Concepts of Striving, Teleology, Final Causes and God





Spinoza explicitly rejects both Aristotelian-style and Medieval-style final causes explanations[i]. So, in this chapter, I shall look at Aristotle’s four causes and Maimonides’ adaptation of it to show how this links in with and influenced Spinoza’s own thinking about teleology.

The topic of teleology and final causes has its roots in Aristotle’s philosophy of science. Aristotle defines final causes as: “an end which is not for the sake of anything else, but for the sake of which everything else is”[ii]. Aristotle points out that final causes, by definition, are finite not infinite and that this gives rise to “reason in the world”[iii] because:

“…the reasonable man always acts for the sake of an end―which is a limit.

Nor, again, can the formal cause be reduced ad infinitum to another definition fuller in expression.”[iv]

He further argues for this by claiming that:

“(ii) To say that it has is to do away with knowledge, because we thereby imply that we cannot know until we reach the unanalysable terms involved in the definition. Scientific knowledge too becomes impossible; how can one conceive of an actually infinite series?”[v]

Aristotle wished to shed light on causation and causal explanations so that, in his capacity as a scientist in his era, he could answer the why questions that arise when examining things in nature as a whole, including various areas of biology and psychology[vi]. On the other hand, in his appendix to part one of the Ethics, Spinoza writes that teleological approaches as riddled with what he calls “praejudicia”[vii]. This is often translated as simply “prejudices”, for instance see White, Stirling’s translation of E. I. app[viii], which I think is roughly correct. However, the literal meaning of the word is a prior judgement, decision or examination which gives me the sense that Spinoza may have meant something along the lines of preconceived ideas. This fits with the context of the word because Spinoza worries that it might get in the way of his readers following his demonstrations[ix]. So I think Spinoza is asking his readers to logically follow his arguments from premises to conclusion without letting their prior biases and judgements interfere with the rational process. He criticises the conclusion that:

“omnes res naturales ut ipsos propter finem agere”[x]

 “…therefore, on that causal account, all things are inherently by nature such that they tend/move/are led (purposefully) to an end/goal” (my translation of E. I. app)

Spinoza then claims (E. I. app): 

“Satis hic erit, si pro fundamento id capiam, quod apud omnes debet esse in confesso; nempe hoc, quod omnes homines rerum causarum ignari nascuntur, et quod omnes appetitum habent suum utile quaerendi, cuius rei sunt conscii.”[xi]

Suffice (adequate) to say (if only to mentally conceive of/ mentally grasp the idea as a foundational basis of thought, which everyone can acknowledge/concede) that everyone is originally formed at birth not knowing/ being unacquainted with/ inexperienced in/ unaware of the cause of things, because/ in so far as everyone instinctively desires/seeks/strives eagerly/longs for what is useful/ profitable/ practical/ helpful/ advantageous/ for them to obtain, which is a phenomenon (something eg event or cause) everyone is (secretly) aware of. (my translation of E. I. app)

So, on Spinoza’s view, this tendency to find out what is profitable leads people to ascribe usefulness and purposefulness to things in the world. This approach to understanding the world can be seen in Aristotle’s Physics[xii], where he puts forward his argument for teleology by claiming that events in nature have a purpose and are useful to us, so it is incoherent to argue that such natural events happen as a result of necessity and are only, by chance, useful to us.

When Aristotle refutes such arguments as incoherent, he is possibly entering into and attempting to further on-going debates by responding to claims such as those made the pre-Socratic, Empedocles. We can see that Empedocles was one of the philosophers Aristotle had in mind because Aristotle provides a summary of Empedocles’s theory of evolution in his Physics (198b29-32)[xiii]. He describes Empedocles’s theory as maintaining that a plethora of living organisms came into existence in the beginning of creation, some of which died out while some survived because they had a use[xiv]. As Bostock points out, Aristotle then tries to refute Empedocles’s theory of evolution by posing a two pronged dilemma for his theory:

“either animals and plants breed true, or they do not. Aristotle insists that the correct answer is that they do (199b13-26), but in that case Empedocles cannot suppose that there ever was a stage of haphazard combinations brought together by Love; for such combinations could only come from the seed of parents of a like kind”[xv].

So, if Empedocles thinks they were “first created” like this, then he can’t explain why they “bred true” afterwards[xvi]. In this way, Aristotle believes that Empedocles’s theory fails because he is arguing for an odd “combination of chance and necessity” which undermines his “mechanism for our evolutionary theory”[xvii]. In this way, Aristotle forces Empedocles to maintain the problematic stance “that regularity can be initiated by chance”[xviii].

However, as Bostock[xix] mentions, Aristotle’s argument here is weak because it overlooks the fact that, just because a regularity appears to be in aid of a particular purpose, it doesn’t follow that this regularity in nature must either be purposeful or due to chance. Bostock[xx] also points out that Democratus could rebut Aristotle by claiming that “regularities in nature are due neither to chance nor to purpose but to necessity”. I think Spinoza has this as a line of counter-argument against Aristotle at his disposal because Spinoza argues for necessity in our nature alongside accounting for human beings’ striving for what they decide or judge to be useful (“utile”, E. IV. p26d[xxi]) to them and to “Conatus sese conservandi” (E. IV. p26d[xxii]). This often used phrase has many potential layers of meaning and implications when you try to translate the meaning of it so I shall break it down into its component words. Conatus can mean an attempt, effort, exertion, struggle but also an impulse or tendency as well as an endeavour, undertaking or enterprise. So perhaps the sense of conatus is a natural tendency we have which gives rise to impulses to keep ourselves (and perhaps each other) safe/spared (from danger), intact/preserved (sese conservandi) which perhaps is addressing the combination of the biological make-up and impulse to endeavour to survive, together with the daily practical struggle for survival before evolutionary theory (both biological and social) became a mainstream view, or the discovery of DNA or detailed case studies in sociology and psychology.

The context of this passage is (E. IV. p26d):

“Conatus sese conservandi nihil est praeter ipsius rei essentiam (per prop. 7. p. 3.), quae quatenus talis existit, vim habere concipitur ad perseverandum in existendo (per prop. 6. p. 3.), et ea agendum, quae ex data sua natura necessario sequuntur.”[xxiii] (italics and accents omitted)

Breaking this down into a literal translation with all meanings included, we see that this passage in Latin argues that the tendency/impulse/struggle to keep ourselves safe (from danger and thereby try to remain intact) is due to our/a thing’s essence. As long as we exist like this, we/a thing will have the power/strength (and imagination/understanding/adopt ways) to continue to exist and to move/act in a way which necessarily comes from our/its nature.

Thus, Spinoza could demonstrate, contra Aristotle, that regularity in nature can be explained through necessity instead of purpose and teleology, without falling into attributing phenomenon to chance.  

In answer to this, Aristotle could reply by maintaining that Democratus can’t account for what is and isn’t useful to us if everything in the world happens necessarily[xxiv]. So, to fill this gap, Aristotle draws a parallel between how nature is set out and human design. This leads Aristotle to claim in the Physics[xxv] that the purpose of the characteristics of living organisms also facilitates their ability to be alive in the first place. Nonetheless, as can be seen in E. IV. p26d[xxvi], Spinoza has the resources in his philosophy to protect his theory against this type of objection by combining these concepts of necessity, usefulness and striving together so that they complement each other rather than conflict with each other.

And Spinoza continues by deducing that:

“…est ergo hic intelligendi conatus (per Coroll. Prop. 22 hujus) primum, et unicum virtutis fundamentum, nec alicujus finis causΓ’ (per Prop. 25. hujus) res intelligere conabimur; sed contrΓ  Mens, quatenus ratiocinatur, nihil sibi bonum esse concipere poterit, nisi id, quo ad intelligendum conducit, (per Defin. I. hujus) Q.E.D.”[xxvii] (italics omitted)

“…this effort to understand is the primary and sole foundation of virtue, and that (Proposition 25, part 4) we do not endeavour to understand things for the sake of an end, but, on the contrary, the mind, in so far as it reasons, can conceive nothing as being good for itself except that which conduces to understanding (Definition I, part 4). Q.E.D.”[xxviii]

Curley has a similar take on how this passage should be translated:

“…this striving for understanding (by P22C) is the first and only foundation of virtue, nor do we strive to understand things for the sake of some end (by P25). On the contrary, the mind, insofar as it reasons, cannot conceive anything to be good for itself except what leads to understanding (by D1) q.e.d.”[xxix]

In this way, the textual evidence in the Ethics (E IVp26d) suggests that Spinoza is saying we necessarily act in accordance with our nature which involves trying to ensure our self-preservation and reasoning our way to rational understanding. This, I think, resolves Aristotle’s conflicts between necessity, purposefulness and apparent chance by showing how necessity and striving for survival cohere.

Furthermore, I suggest that Spinoza suffers even less than Empedocles, and even Darwin and modern science at times, from Aristotle’s criticism of those who hold the two contradictory premises that nature’s regularities were propelled by chance. For instance, this tension can also be resolved by reconceptualising Spinoza’s premises in the appendix to E. I[xxx] in the way I outline below:

 Nature’s regularities are the result of the laws of nature which flow from God because God is the only cause. God and so the laws of nature act necessarily not contingently thus dictating human behaviour and the natural world in a regular, patterned way and not by chance. What seems to us like chance, reflects our lack of understanding about the laws of nature rather than it being symptomatic of any random workings of God or the natural world. Nothing is purely random and, strictly speaking, there is a reason and explanation for everything so, if it seems random, the problem is that the phenomenon is merely beyond our current understanding of natural phenomenon. This dissolves the contradiction of regularity seemingly coming from pure chance.

 Indeed, even today, modern science can sometimes assume that, for instance, which genetic traits or illnesses we inherit can be due to brute luck and chance, rather than seeing these apparently haphazard results as potentially due to causes that are currently unknown to science. Genes are capable of mutating or switching on and off during our lifetime, sometimes due to environmental factors. So I suggest that a Spinozian approach; encompassing necessity, attempting to understand obscure laws of nature and perhaps seeing our nature, DNA and genomes as striving to persevere in their being, including by changing and adapting; may be a helpful conceptual apparatus for scientific progress in this field. I think Spinoza also coheres with scientific thought when he claims nothing strives to destroy itself. When this seems to occur, it is probably due to external factors or is symptomatic of something going wrong, giving rise to this abnormality of self-destruction.        

Nevertheless, contemporary theories of evolution could try to evade Aristotle’s criticism on their own terms by highlighting that, as Bostock points out, “From our evolutionary perspective, the ‘purpose served’ is not so much the survival of the individual as the survival of the species, or what comes to the same thingthe successful reproduction of the individual”[xxxi] (italics  in original). However, I suggest Spinoza has a more well-rounded approach in his Ethics and TTP by acknowledging that both individuals and collectives can strive so we can potentially better explain the range of different ways we strive to survive as individuals, collectively as groups as well as a wider political state[xxxii]. I interpret Spinoza arguments as retaining more flexibility and function in the way he is asking us to apply them if we see his conatus doctrine/concept of striving as an eclectic, cluster concept which spans a range of domains including the social, biological, political, psychological, ethical, practical, epistemological and metaphysical aspects of life all rolled into one.  

For Spinoza, not only does his account of necessity apply to the laws of nature studied in science but, unlike Aristotle, it also applies to a monotheistic God. Spinoza argues in his Preface to E. IV.[xxxiii] that God is eternal and so His actions do not constitute final causes but, instead, come about from necessity.  In this way, Spinoza[xxxiv] argues that, since God’s actions and existence are not teleological, final causes are invented by people because they want to understand what is useful to them as well as how things in the world happen and why. This can be seen explicitly in his Ethics when he writes:

“Ut iam autem ostendam, naturam finem nullum sibi praefixum habere, et omnes causas finales nihil nisi humana esse figmenta, non opus est multis.”[xxxv]

“…nature has set no end before herself, and that all final causes are nothing but human fictions.”[xxxvi]    

Figmenta can mean any of the following words: figment, fiction, invention, unreality; thing formed/devised; image. Different translators choose different words for it. I think it is interesting to think which word captures Spinoza’s meaning here best because it carries different implications accordingly. Is Spinoza saying that final causes are like a figment of our imagination, or something that arises from our imaginative capacities (in terms of the seventeenth century philosophy usage of imagination), or that they are like fictional stories we create, or are they something we invent, or that final causes are like an image, or that they are unreal and so are not a phenomenon that happens in reality? This would also impact on the type of claim Spinoza is making, for instance, a claim about reality would be metaphysical but if it were about imagination or fictions it could be an epistemic, psychological, philosophy of mind claim and fictions would potentially involve truth claims more than reality claims. What type of error is involved in believing in final causes, according to Spinoza? It could be argued that it is a psychological error given he attributes final causes to human desire (the word Spinoza chose was appetitum, so perhaps more precisely he may mean a natural, instinctive desire which suggests a more biological reason for this desire). 



This passage comes much later on, in his preface to part four of the Ethics:

“Causa autem, quae finalis dicitur, nihil est praeter ipsum humanum appetitum, quatenus is alicuius rei veluti principium seu causa primaria consideratur.”[xxxvii]

“A final cause, as it is called, is nothing, therefore, but human desire…”[xxxviii] (transl. White/Stirling)

“What is called a final cause is nothing but a human appetite…”[xxxix] (transl. Curley)

This contrasts with medieval views, namely Maimonides who considers God to be “the final cause of the universe”[xl] (hereafter referred to as Guide) and so certainly not a human desire or fiction, as Spinoza suggests in his Ethics. Maimonides argues that the telos of “the series of the successive purposes” is the “wisdom” or will of God[xli]. So, Maimonides concludes that “Consequently, God is the final purpose of everything” and that “God is…the End of all ends.”[xlii] In this way, Maimonides’ Medieval-style teleology is a different approach to teleology from Ancient Greek and Early Modern approaches in that, unlike the former, it argues for a monotheistic God and unlike the later, it takes a broad-brush approach to divine teleology.  I think Spinoza would agree with Maimonides that God is causally prior to all things. However, Maimonides’ Medieval-style teleology is distinct in style in that it is wider in scope and outlines specific teleological arguments for a monotheistic God, unlike Aristotelian teleology. I shall compare and contrast the ways in which Spinoza selectively agrees and disagrees with Maimonides about other notions surrounding final causes. Spinoza, unlike Maimonides, views teleology as limiting God to being anthropomorphic-like. So, he refutes all types of linear, final cause style explanations in favour of an account of God’s non-linear eternity, existence and omnipotence that isn’t restricted to specific goals to explain intentional human behaviour and the natural world around us. Therefore, I base my approach on Spinoza’s Preface to E IV and his appendix to E. I[xliii] when he writes that God is eternal and so does not act in terms of final causes but rather via necessity.

Spinoza argues for this in three vitally different ways, in various sections of the Ethics, which he sees as strengthening the omnipotence and perfection of God.

One, Spinoza refutes divine teleology and explicitly claims that, if God did have an intellect or will then it wouldn’t function or be able to be described in such a human-like way because God’s intellect and will is so different from ours that the comparison is as absurd and inaccurate as drawing parallels between “the celestial constellation of the Dog and the animal which barks” (“quam inter se conveniunt canis, signum coeleste, et canis, animal latrans”, E. I. p17s[xliv]).

By reducing God’s nature in this way, we unintentionally and unwittingly reduce God’s perfection.



To illustrate how he refutes divine teleology, I shall set out his argument in his Ethics logically (see A., B., and C. below).

I have formulated A to C myself by organising Spinoza’s premises in his arguments into the following logical argument frameworks to expose the structure of Spinoza’s rejection of teleology by demonstrating how it could also be presented as:

A)     a classical-style (ie Ancient Greek especially used in mathematics) reductio ad absurdum

B)      a doctrinal annihilation (ie a group of propositions that taken together are inconsistent with one another)

C)      Spinoza’s positive argument as a deduction





A) Spinoza’s argument against divine teleology set out as a classical reductio ad absurdum:

Premise 1) Suppose God acts in a teleological way (with the purpose of acting for end goals/ a telos)

Premise 2) We know that God is eternal (which by definition excludes having an ending, final point to aim at), omnipotent and necessary (not contingent)

Premise 3) This means that God, from His nature/essence, is eternal and acts, in accordance with His essence/nature, from necessity and omnipotence.

Premise 4) But this means that God does not act in a linear, teleological way that aims at special goals/ends because it is not consistent with His eternal, omnipotent, necessary nature, which is contrary to the hypothesis stated in 1) that God acts in a teleological way

Premise 5) Hence, given the hypothesis in premise 1 leads to a logical contradiction, it must be rejected.

Premise 6) In this way, the thesis that God does not act in a teleological way for final goals/ends is established.



B) Spinoza’s argument against teleology set out as a doctrinal annihilation:   

God → telos

Telos → final ends/goals

Final ends/goals → eternity

Not eternity

But this leads to the contradiction that God is not eternal (because eternity does not involve a final end point) so the hypothesis that God acts in a teleological way leads to an absurdity so must be rejected as it has been shown to be logically refutable.

So, I suggest Spinoza’s positive version of the aforementioned negative argument could also be presented deductively from axioms to conclusion in the following way:



C) Spinoza’s positive argument as a deduction:

Premise 1: It is self-evident that God is eternal.

Premise 2: Eternity, by definition, has no end point/telos to aim at.

Premise 3: It is self-evident that God exists necessarily not contingently.

Premise 4: From premise 3 it follows that God acts necessarily not contingently (because God acts from His essence/nature (E I) which is necessary not contingent).

Therefore: God’s existence is necessary and eternal and so His actions involve necessity and do not aim at a telos/end goal.

In this way, Spinoza argues[xlv] that, since there is no telos to God’s actions or existence, final causes are invented by humans because they desire to understand what is useful to them and how things happen and why. Spinoza notes that when humans view the world as existing in a way that is useful to them, they go on to suppose that God set it out for them. This leads to appeasing God in a superstitious way in order that the world functions in a way that is useful to them and favours them rather than incurring divine retribution.

Therefore, teleology has important implications for and impact on Spinoza’s discussion of true worship and superstition. So, although Spinoza rejects teleology per se because it involves the notion that an anthropomorphic God is directing humans and the world through divine providence, he still considers his views as being in line with true religion, partly because it avoids falling into false worship and superstitious attitudes, beliefs and actions. Moreover, Spinoza thinks his account leads to a strengthened belief in God because he claims that a teleological account “does away with God’s perfection”[xlvi] (“Deinde haec doctrina Dei perfectionem tollit”[xlvii] [destroys, removes]). He views divine teleology as restricting God to being “in need”[xlviii] of something other than Himself.

“Deinde haec doctrina Dei perfectionem tolli: Nam, si Deus propter finem agit, aliquid necessario appetit, quo caret.”[xlix] (E. I. app) (accents omitted)

So here we see that Spinoza is arguing that we remove and thereby destroy God’s perfection if we see God as acting (agit) for an end goal (finem) because this means He is seeking/striving /longing for/desiring (appetit) a thing which He lacks/ is devoid of/ absent from/ is without (caret). This last word is interesting because it highlights the contradiction: how can God be perfect if He lacks something? Perfection would mean not lacking anything, a lack surely implies an imperfection. Therefore Spinoza thinks he has logically proven that, since God is perfect, He cannot lack anything so can’t be teleologically striving for or desiring anything. Striving, desiring and lacking, amongst other descriptions of Him, also makes God anthropomorphic-like. So, Spinoza provides an alternative metaphysical account by replacing all types of linear, final cause style explanations with a thorough-going account of God’s non-linear eternity, existence, omnipotence and perfection. Furthermore, Spinoza considers himself to have entirely (omnino) overthrown/overturned/turned upside down (evertere) the doctrine of final causes, especially when he adds that it conflates causes and effects by misattributing one to the other[l]. The word caret may also carry the implication that God is never, strictly speaking absent, which would fit with the concepts in panentheism, a debate I address in the next chapter.  

Two, another reason Spinoza rejects teleology in the Appendix to E I[li] is that it also reduces God’s perfection by inculcating superstition. This happens because, while attempting to figure out what is profitable for them, people ascribe to “the gods” the desire to “direct everything for” the benefit of humans and so think teleologically and look for final causes[lii]. Such teleological “praeiudicium” (prejudice, prejudgement), Spinoza argues, becomes “superstitionem”, meaning literally superstition or irrational religious awe[liii]. This passage perhaps also leads support for Spinoza’s arguments in his TTP[liv] about the value of using our rational faculties in religion to avoid superstition. In this way, people end up falsely believing that how they worship impacts on the gods’ mood and how well disposed they are to humans which in turn affects their fortunes in life as well as being the cause of extreme weather conditions[lv]. This, for Spinoza, constitutes another form of lessening “God’s perfection” because “if God works to obtain an end, He necessarily seeks something of which he stands in need”[lvi]. This often leads to self-contradiction anyway since exponents of this view also maintain that “God has done all things for His own sake, and not for the sake of the things to be created, because before the creation they can assign nothing excepting God for the sake of which God could do anything…”[lvii]. Much as Maimonides[lviii] argues for divine purpose, he would also reject any attempts to pander to God’s supposed supernatural powers as constituting superstition. So, I suggest Spinoza here is in agreement with Maimonides concerning forms of superstitious behaviour and tendencies, but Spinoza is trying to carry this through consistently in his arguments by going on to refute the teleological, purposeful motives behind God’s actions. This reformulation of Maimonides is not as far removed from Maimonides’ views as it first appears to be since Maimonides would agree with Spinoza that it is not in God’s nature to be at the mercy of emotion.   

Three, for Spinoza, technically metaphysically speaking, there is only cause and that cause is God. This is a pivotal concept in Spinoza’s thought and has various consequences for many of his philosophical claims and outlook. For instance, In E. I. p24c[lix], Spinoza explicitly argues that “God only is the cause”, whether this be in relation to things first coming into existence, their existence per se, or “their continuance in existence” which Spinoza links with God as the cause of Being when he writes “(...scholastic phraseology) God is the causa essendi rerum”.

Given Spinoza’s above views, I think he may agree with Maimonides about Judaism’s notion of creation being on-going (termed constant creation) because he views God as continually and actively causing things to exist and act. Jewish views about constant creation can be gleaned from certain prayers, such as the Modeh Ani, thanking God for renewing you so you continue to exist and live another day. Spinoza has perhaps merely adapted the doctrine of constant creation so that, rather than limiting God to having a human-like will, His “infinite nature” has “supreme power” and all things “have necessarily flowed, or continually follow by the same necessity”[lx] (omnia necessario effluxisse, vel semper eadem necessitate sequi[lxi] [E. I. p17s]). In this way, Spinoza explicitly claims that he has “far more firmly established” “the omnipotence of God” by arguing that God is and always has and always will continually be eternal, perhaps together with the implications of being imperishable and perpetual[lxii] (Dei omnipotentia actu ab aeterno fuit et in aeternum in eadem actualitate manebit[lxiii]). This is derived from proposition 17 and its demonstration which clearly states that everything flows necessarily from God’s divine nature in an unconstrained and infinite number of ways[lxiv]. This impacts on Spinoza’s account of things in the world because God is “the free cause of all things…all things are in Him, and so depend upon Him…and…all things have been predetermined by Him…from His absolute nature or infinite power”[lxv]. Moreover, in E. I. p29[lxvi] he claims that “all things are determined from the necessity of the divine nature to exist and act in a certain manner”. In the demonstration to this proposition[lxvii] Spinoza makes his controversial and hotly debated claim “Whatever is, is in God”. This is often interpreted as a pantheistic claim which identifies God and nature as being numerically identical or in other words, one and the same thing. This can cause all sorts of interpretative problems when assessing Spinoza on teleology, final causes and God so I shall be examining this in the next chapter. 





[i] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), chap. E. I. app; E. IV pref.
[ii] Aristotle, Metaphysics, 364.
[iii] Aristotle, 364.
[iv] Aristotle, 364.
[v] Aristotle, 364 (ii).
[vi] Barnes, “Aristotle” A Very Short Introduction.
[vii] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I app, 116.
[viii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I app, 35.
[ix] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I app.
[x] Spinoza and Krop, E. I. app.
[xi] Spinoza and Krop, E. I. app.
[xii] Aristotle, Physics, chap. 8, 198b10-29.
[xiii] Aristotle, 198b29-32.
[xiv] Aristotle, 198b29-32.
[xv] Bostock, “Introduction and Explanatory Notes,” xxvii.
[xvi] Bostock, xxvii.
[xvii] Bostock, xxvii.
[xviii] Bostock, xxvii.
[xix] Bostock, footnote 16, xxvii.
[xx] Bostock, xxvii.
[xxi] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E IVp26d.
[xxii] Spinoza and Krop, E. IV. p26d.
[xxiii] Spinoza and Krop, E. IV. p26d.
[xxiv] Aristotle, Physics, chap. 8, 199a8 f.
[xxv] Aristotle, Physics.
[xxvi] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. IV. p26d.
[xxvii] Spinoza and Krop, E. IV. p26d.
[xxviii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. IV. p26d.
[xxix] Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics, ed. and trans. Edwin Curley, Penguin Classics, Penguin Books (England, UK: Penguin Books, 1996), E. IV. p26d.
[xxx] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. app.
[xxxi] Bostock, “Introduction and Explanatory Notes,” footnote 17, xxvii.
[xxxii] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica; Spinoza, Opera: TTP.
[xxxiii] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. IV. pref.
[xxxiv] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica.
[xxxv] Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. I. app.
[xxxvi] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. app.
[xxxvii] Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. IV pref; Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. IV. pref., 344
[xxxviii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. IV. pref, 162.
[xxxix] Spinoza, Ethics, Transl. Curley, E. I. pref., pref.114.
[xl] M. Maimonides, The Guide for the Perplexed, ed. Andrew Meit and David Reed, trans. M. Friedlander, second edition (e-book), 1904, Chap. LXIX, 196, http://www.teachittome.com/seforim2/seforim/the_guide_for_the_perplexed.pdf.
[xli] Maimonides, 198.
[xlii] Maimonides, 198.
[xliii] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. IV pref; E. I. app; Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. IV. pref; E. I. app.
[xliv] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. p17s; Spinoza, Opera: Ethics.
[xlv] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica.
[xlvi] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. app, 38.
[xlvii] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. app.
[xlviii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. app, 38.
[xlix] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. app, 120; Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. I. app.
[l] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. app; Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. I. app.
[li] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. app; Spinoza, Opera: Ethics.
[lii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. app, 36.
[liii] Spinoza and Krop, Spinoza Ethica, E. I. app; Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. I. app.
[liv] Spinoza, TTP Trans. Elwes; Spinoza, Opera: TTP.
[lv] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. app, 37.
[lvi] Spinoza, E. I app, 38.
[lvii] Spinoza, E. I. app, 38.
[lviii] Maimonides, The Guide for the Perplexed.
[lix] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. p24c.
[lx] Spinoza, E. I. p17s, 20.
[lxi] Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. I. p17s, 202.
[lxii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. p17s, 20.
[lxiii] Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:E. I. p17s, 203.
[lxiv] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), E. I. p17; E. I. p17s.
[lxv] Spinoza, E.I. app, 35.
[lxvi] Spinoza, E. I. p29.
[lxvii] Spinoza, E. I. p29d.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.