Saturday, 8 September 2018

Spinoza vol 2 ebook Chapter 4: The Psychological Impact of Fear and Anxiety on Freedom, Living Wisely, Dying Well and Attaining Eternity in Spinoza’s Ethics


Chapter 4: The Psychological Impact of Fear and Anxiety on Freedom, Living Wisely, Dying Well and Attaining Eternity in Spinoza’s Ethics  


In this chapter, I shall explore how EVp38 highlights the relationship between knowledge (cognitionis) and fear of death (mortem … timet). Breaking the concepts down, we see that the phrase fear of death in this proposition involves narrowing down negative emotions to a verb that particularly specifies fear (timeo), while the noun death (mors) incorporates the topics of corpses and, more generally, annihilation. Fear is a negative, harmful affect so builds on the general problem of negative affects raised earlier in the proposition EVp38. In his definitions of the affects in EIII, Spinoza lists two different words, both of which can carry the meaning of fear.

So what are the possible meanings of these two words? The first definition, which involves fear, is the thirteenth definition, “metus”[i] which can mean fear, dread, apprehension, anxiety, and terror. It can also refer to religious awe although this is usually in poetry. The second definition which involves fear is “timor”, which appears in definition thirty nine[ii], and comes from the verb timeo. The literal meaning of timor is mainly fear and dread although this can include apprehension, alarm, anxiety. Timor can also sometimes carry the meaning of timidity although this is a lesser-used equivalent word in English. It can be used in personification and when conveying that an object arouses fear, terror or anxiety, especially when used in poetry. It can be used to convey an emotion for positive reasons too, namely awe, reverence, veneration and is related to the word timoratus meaning that one is full of reverence towards God, god-fearing, devout and reverent. As far as I can gather, Spinoza does not use two other main words for fear which he could have used, such as terror, terroris meaning terror/fear/alarm/panic and pavor, pavoris meaning fear/panic.

Why does this matter? It gives us a more complex, nuanced idea of what Spinoza may have meant by fearing death and how it relates to attempting to live well and die well. I think it might also impact generally on the way we read Spinoza and understand him, especially since translations of Spinoza’s definitions of the affects in EIII varies. White and Sterling[iii] translate both metus in definition thirteen and timor in definition thirty nine as fear. I think this is confusing and unhelpful because it gives the erroneous impression that Spinoza repeats himself and conflates his terms by  en  explore how liate scrub up giving two different definitions of the same word. Curley[iv] and Elwes[v] chose to give the two definitions separate senses, making metus mean fear and timor mean timidity. This has the advantage of keeping the definitions separate and showing that Spinoza uses two different words and does not conflate his terms. Timidity is not a central meaning of timor but perhaps somewhat gives us the flavour of Spinoza’s definition of it. Nevertheless, a drawback is that using timidity could somewhat disassociate timor from its direct meaning of fear. Thereby, making timor sound more like a personality trait rather than something arising from a fear of an object external to you which is impacting on your emotions and judgement in a way that you need to learn to control. Timidity may be a by-product of this situation and reaction but, I claim, that Spinoza’s definition of timor is more layered than the simple definition of being too timid would suggest.   

Hence, I shall now analyse: How does Spinoza word his philosophical definitions of metus and timor and how does it relate to the linguistic meanings and connotations of these words? What does this tell us about Spinoza’s views on thinking about and fearing death? 

Spinoza defines the word metus as “tristitia”[vi] whose main meaning is sadness, although tristitia is also used in Latin to mean mournfulness, sorrow, grief, melancholy, gloom, dejection, moroseness and it has similar connotations to its synonym severitas, so both can imply severity, sternness and harshness. Spinoza himself generally defines tristitia in his third definition of the affects in EIII as referring to people passing from a greater, more powerful ideal or perfection to a lesser one[vii]. He specifies that one suffers from metus erratically, because he adds the adjective inconstans meaning changeable, inconstant, inconsistent, capricious[viii]. Metus originates from ideas of the future or past whose outcome/fate/success we doubt to some degree[ix]. In his definition[x], he refers back to EIIIp18s2 so we are meant to expand his definition by relating it to this scholium. EIIIp18s2[xi] adds that metus springs from an image of a doubtful/ dubious/ uncertain/ variable/ dangerous/ critical (dubiae) thing/event (rei). If one were to remove the element of doubt then metus would become despair[xii].

However, when Spinoza defines timor in EIIIdef39, he narrows his definition to an ambition/eagerness/ (carnal) desire to take the path of a lesser evil to avoid/evade a greater evil (malum, which can also mean apple so perhaps has connotations of Adam and Eve especially since Spinoza discussed the Garden of Eden in the Ethics) out of fear (metuimus from metuo, related to metus). To gain further insight into the meaning of timor, Spinoza refers us to EIIIp39s[xiii]. There we see a more detailed example of how timor impacts on judgement and actions. Spinoza uses the verb form of timor, which is timeat from timeo and not metus. He gives the example of someone who is filled with hate but after considering/planning it, meditating/reflecting on it, s/he chooses not to injure another for fear that they will suffer a greater evil themselves than their intended target (EIIIp39s[xiv]).

This example makes me question whether timidity is a good fit here for what Spinoza is describing with the word timor. In this example in EIIIp39s, the person does not come across as timid but rather seems to be under the influence of strongly negative passions such as hate, and perhaps revenge, while being very self-centred, worrying more about how it will impact on themselves rather than truly reflecting on the right thing to do. The person may be timid, in the sense of lacking courage to do a certain action (call it φ), but it is not very timid of them to want to φ purely out of hatred for another. Indeed, it’s probably best that they decide against φing! Acting out of hatred for another cannot lead to ethical action or justice. For instance, Spinoza argues that judges should make a ruling by seeing the wider picture and considering and loving what is in the “public well-being” and use their rational faculties to decide such matters, rather than act out of “hatred or anger” (EIVp63c,d[xv]). In this way, we can better avoid evil by aligning our desire with reason (EIVp63c[xvi]). Since Spinoza argues in EIVp64[xvii] that knowledge of evil is always inadequate knowledge (especially, I maintain, since evil does not give us knowledge of God because evil is not an attribute of God), perhaps the problem Spinoza is exploring here is that thinking about φ and choosing to φ or not to φ becomes fraught if one is in the grips of negative affects such as hatred and anger and therefore working off inadequate knowledge. Yet φing is a recurrent aspect of life and letting fear lead one into inadequate knowledge and negative affects, which consequently muddles ones cognition and judgement, makes one less intelligent and inhibits one’s ability to live well, acquire true, adequate knowledge and act piously and ethically. It also reduces our eternity by lowering the percentage of second and third kinds of knowledge we possess so decreasing the eternity of our mind and soul. So we not only live less well, we also die less well and are less eternal after life.

Furthermore, a main difference which strikes me between Spinoza’s two words for fear is that timor is more related to cognition than metus. Interestingly, for the topic of free will, it is describing choosing between two options (call them whether to φ or ψ) and choices of action (φing or ψing). So Spinoza must be leaving room for freedom of choice and action within his account of necessity. Metus is used to help define timor hence timor is perhaps also different in the sense that, although it is also a term of fear, in Spinoza’s definitions, it helps him refer to the negative impact fear has on our cognitive capacities and hence our life choices and decision-making of whether to φ or not. The question remains: Why did he choose both metus as well as timor for his main definitions of the affect, fear? I maintain that Spinoza uses the more all-encompassing word for fear, metus, as a definition because he is giving an overall definition of fear from which he extracts timor, giving it a narrower definition to show the cognitive impact of the negative affect of fear and anxiety. Then he can expand on both these aspects of fear more clearly to construct various arguments to fit the context when discussing a topic. For instance, in EIVp67 and its demonstration[xviii] Spinoza could have used the noun timor, timoris meaning fear/dread (which would be in keeping with its related verb timeo, timere, timui which he uses in EVp38, see “timet”[xix]) when discussing a fear of death in relation to wise or free people, but instead, he uses metus. However, in EVp38, he uses timeo when discussing a fear/dread of death. By analysing Spinoza’s definitions, it becomes clearer that timor, with its cognitive and epistemological implications of thinking and knowing how to act, fits with the clash between true, adequate knowledge and fear which Spinoza is highlighting in EVp38 and elsewhere in the Ethics. In his works, there is often a close tie between knowledge and fear which works both ways. True, adequate knowledge helps reduce fear while inadequate ideas generate fear and superstition. Conversely, combatting fear and superstition promotes true, adequate knowledge whereas a rise in fear and superstition, be it in our individual life or collectively as a society, reduces our intelligence and perpetuates false, inadequate ideas. Although Spinoza gives examples of individuals, it is cross-applicable to the collective in wider society. Spinoza is showing the damaging effects of fear on people, irrespective of whether it arises from other negative affects such as hatred or whether it is the climate of fear which triggers negative affects such as anger and hatred alongside poor cognition. Moreover, Spinoza would rather one does not act out of fear or try to evade evil, even if the result is that a person is φing by bringing about a good (EIVp63[xx]). So, leaving aside the aspect of hatred in EIIIp39s for a moment, one can see how timor and metus could cloud anyone’s intellect through negativity and poor coping strategies in the face of stress, fear and, I suggest, anxiety. Both metus and timor can refer to anxiety but, given his definitions, I suggest my above examination helps us to distinguish between feeling anxious or fearful (metus) and acting out of fear and anxiety (timor), revealing the practical application of Spinoza’s philosophy of emotion on living and dying well.

Thus: Is Spinoza somewhat philosophising about the psychology of stress and anxiety and how to alleviate it yourself, by managing your negative affects, including reducing the effect fear has on your cognition and judgement, in order to live well and die well? I contend that Spinoza has captured a common but lesser-known aspect of human nature and psychology with his analysis of fear and its impact on mental cognition and knowledge. I think this is impressive and insightful of Spinoza, especially since it is still an on-going debate in psychology today. I suggest that findings in recent studies perhaps support Spinoza’s philosophy of emotion and psychology which I have outlined above.  

Scientific research has shown that fear and stress has a detrimental impact on cognition and memory. The fight or flight reaction is designed to help us act rather than reason, especially when it involves using our reasoning faculties to take in, understand and remember new knowledge[xxi]. Spinoza specifically discusses the now well-known psychological phenomenon of fight or flight. In EIVp69c, Spinoza maintains:

“The free man is as courageous in timely retreat as in combat; or, a free man shows equal courage or presence of mind, whether he elect to give battle or to retreat.”[xxii]

Such presence of mind is an ability which is just as relevant today as it was in Spinoza’s era and is a very important survival skill. In this way, Spinoza picks up on something fundamental in psychology when developing his account of the free man, living well and wisely despite conflict or any dangerous situations which may arise. Psychology research has discovered that fear can make people “suffer cognitive paralysis, resulting in complete inaction.”[xxiii] A familiar example of this in daily life is when a fire alarm goes off in a building and people stop what they are doing but, instead of evacuating the building,  slump into inaction and negativity. Even if it later turns out to be a false alarm, your overall survival strategy should be to go through standard evacuation procedures calmly and efficiently. Although you may encounter several false alarms and may not want to look silly constantly evacuating unnecessarily, it only takes one correct alert to be fatal and you will not find out which one that is until it is too late. Therefore, people are advised to leave their office when the alarm goes off, whether they feel like doing so or not[xxiv]. However, extrapolating from the aforementioned scientific research, I deduce that actively beginning an evacuation is more likely to be the response of stress-hardy people who, unlike the majority of people, are less prone to freezing during dangerous, stressful, fear-inducing situations. Furthermore, I maintain that Spinoza would advise that one should not just think of oneself when the alarm goes off but help those slower to respond so “they escape from the dangers”[xxv].

Perhaps another cause of misresponding to pressure situations could be related to Morgan’s discovery in a study carried out in 2006[xxvi]. He found that the side-effect of fear on cognitive ability and information retention meant participants struggled to see the wider picture and tended to only remember and focus on small specifics which changed the way they would, for instance, reproduce a drawing from memory[xxvii]. This concurs with other studies carried out which show the impact fear and anxiety has on memory and cognitive performance[xxviii]. Some suggested approaches for alleviating anxiety and depression and reducing the negative impact it has on the intellect is, I claim, in line with Spinoza. I argue that Spinoza’s appreciation of the complexity of fear, anxiety and depression being a combination of emotional, behavioural and cognitive factors is supported by a number of studies and experiments carried out in modern psychology. This field is still a work in progress and there is much still to be done. However, some studies have shown that making changes to your cognitive approach is often particularly effective and important for both physical and mental health, regardless of whether someone is clinically or non-clinically depressed or anxious[xxix]. Even mild, non-clinical depression or anxiety can adversely impact on intellectual performance, for instance in exams, so examination bodies and institutions are advised to do everything they can to help reduce potential stressors so it does not lower students’ academic performance[xxx]. In terms of therapeutic approaches and what individuals can do to help themselves, some experiment results indicate the importance of dealing with doubt and negativity while reshuffling one’s cognitive functioning, alongside dealing with emotional factors[xxxi]. Hence, I think Spinoza was right to combat depression, anxiety and factors impeding cognitive and intellectual development by taking the same three factors as modern psychology does into account, namely, emotional, cognitive and behavioural. These three factors, I maintain, are not only reflected in his double definition of fear and related responses (metus, timor), but also in his descriptions of various emotional, behavioural as well as cognitive thought processes which he argues need addressing in order to live well.   

When it comes to more extreme, dangerous fight or flight situations, studies have found that it is useful for people to learn how to cope during extreme fear-inducing situations, as, for instance, soldiers do, because you are significantly less likely to make potentially fatal errors and you generally increase your survival chances, although differences remain even between skilled soldiers[xxxii]. Reactions to fear-inducing scenarios vary more markedly among untrained people, in relation to their prior cognitive abilities and personality traits[xxxiii].

There is, however, disagreement about how anxious people fare.

Robinson finds that anxious people perform worse because their cognition and memory is too preoccupied with thinking about their fear of dying[xxxiv]. In this way, Robinson’s plausible account of the anxious experiencing a decrease in their cognitive abilities through a fear of death, I think, lends support to Spinoza’s claim in EIVp67 that a free, wise person would not dwell on thinking about death or be overtaken by negative affects, including worrying about and fearing death.

However, Derakhshan adds that anxious people have one extra skill over non-anxious people. Derakhshan argues that people who suffer from anxiety have the “advantage” of being better at detecting something hostile and acting swiftly[xxxv]. Nevertheless, I’m not convinced that anxious people always accurately perceive who and what is and is not hostile and react appropriately. Surely they may either be prone to panicking or be made to panic. Or simply assume the worst due to their negative brain pattern or based on bad experiences in the past, rather than inferring it accurately from the people and situation presented to them. However, I agree that they need not be passive victims who require others to deal with potential situations for them, given that anxious people possibly retain the ability to detect and act on a problem, in other words, think and act for themselves under pressure. Indeed, throughout the Ethics, Spinoza encourages the wisdom of pursuing an independent, rational, measured approach over irrational, hysterical reactions, brought-on by fear and negative affects, which impair wisdom and knowledge and directly or indirectly generate evil. This is a central message of EVp38 which highlights the connection between knowledge and negative affects, encompassing anxiety, dread and fear, including a fear of death.


[i] Benedict de Spinoza, Opera, Renati des cartes principia philosophiae more geometrico demonstrata Cogitata metaphysica  Ethica ordine geometrico demonstrata, ed. C.H. Bruder, EX EDITIONIBUS PRINCIPIBUS DENUO EDIDIT EDITIO STEREOTYPA. (google e-book), vol. I (Leipzig, Germany: TYPIS ET SUMTIBUS BERNH. TAUCHNITZ JUN., 1843), 320, https://books.googleusercontent.com/books/content?req=AKW5QaepYJ2v89MStBAazNfXFlh7XPUFnaSpDsdzbmMb4u8oZ4OmK4Wf3qk49paF5UhkgDGPR-WCy1g3iJtEYf8FSV6uKDrfcAhNPaej4SHS_GB-AKc6L0dbARc08wB15nPpojJE1BHJoSMMnqO5KrXeTM1bCZSqG4dgkeKN-791cBRdLqfymhDLPcXpm3tA6nCh14r7Vqor_6Q5aD6Tal8Jp-5cIESXEEfw-aJVpRq01WBZu-CT7KvAnYUGv6qTXDcGgVuk6D2tGhqM_JNWxQKuY5hx30cClePoudB83HZjCouCbaOC9_c.
[ii] Spinoza, I:325.
[iii] Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics, trans. W.H. White and A.K. Stirling, Wordsworth Classics of World Literature (Great Britain: Wordsworth Editions, 2001), 149, 155.
[iv] Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics, ed. and trans. Edwin Curley, Penguin Classics, Penguin Books (England, UK: Penguin Books, 1996), 106, 111.
[v] Benedict de Spinoza, THE CHIEF WORKS of BENEDICT DE SPINOZA, trans. R. H. M. Elwes, REVISED EDITION. London, UK, vol. II, BOHN’S PHILOSOPHICAL LIBRARY. SPINOZA’S WORKS. (London: york street, covent garden new york: 66, fifth avenue, and bombay: 53, esplanade road cambridge: deighton, bell & co: GEORGE BELL & SONS, 1901), 167, 182, http://lf-oll.s3.amazonaws.com/titles/1711/1321.02_Bk.pdf.
[vi] Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:320.
[vii] Spinoza, I:317.
[viii] Spinoza, I:320.
[ix] Spinoza, I:320.
[x] Spinoza, I:320.
[xi] Spinoza, I:286.
[xii] Spinoza, I:286.
[xiii] Spinoza, I:299–300.
[xiv] Spinoza, I:299–300.
[xv] Spinoza, THE CHIEF WORKS of BENEDICT DE SPINOZA, II:231.
[xvi] Spinoza, II:230.
[xvii] Spinoza, II:231.
[xviii] Spinoza, Ethics (Transl. White, Stirling), 212.
[xix] Spinoza, Opera: Ethics, I:411.
[xx] Spinoza, THE CHIEF WORKS of BENEDICT DE SPINOZA, II:230.
[xxi] Michael Bond, ‘In the Face of Danger’, New Scientist, 13 May 2017.
[xxii] Spinoza, THE CHIEF WORKS of BENEDICT DE SPINOZA, II:233.
[xxiii] Bond, ‘In the Face of Danger’, 33.
[xxiv] Bond, ‘In the Face of Danger’.
[xxv] Spinoza, THE CHIEF WORKS of BENEDICT DE SPINOZA, II:210.
[xxvi] Bond, ‘In the Face of Danger’.
[xxvii] Bond.
[xxviii] Esther F. Akinsola and Augustina D. Nwajei, ‘Test Anxiety, Depression and Academic Performance: Assessment and Management Using Relaxation and Cognitive Restructuring Techniques’, Psychology 4, no. 6A1 (2013): 18–24, https://doi.org/http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/psych.2013.46A1003.
[xxix] Akinsola and Nwajei, 23.
[xxx] Akinsola and Nwajei, 23.
[xxxi] Akinsola and Nwajei, ‘Test Anxiety, Depression and Academic Performance: Assessment and Management Using Relaxation and Cognitive Restructuring Techniques’.
[xxxii] Bond, ‘In the Face of Danger’.
[xxxiii] Bond.
[xxxiv] Bond.
[xxxv] Bond, 35.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.