Tuesday 9 January 2018

Spinoza vol 1 ebook Chapter 1: The Analytic Philosophical Methodology in My Analytic-Jewish Interpretation 





In this Chapter, I adopt the “familiar analytic mode”[i] for furthering a debate by critically engaging with existing literature and outlining my stance by comparing and contrasting my approach and discussion of Spinoza with others, namely Nadler, Susan James and Scruton, in the spirit of an ideal held by analytic philosophy as described by Lamarque and Olsen:

“There is a sense of community among contributors to these debates, however overtly critical analytic philosophers can seem of each other’s work. Progress comes through criticism, often in the form of unexpected counterexamples to general theses. Jenefer Robinson’s paper on “Expression and Arousal of Emotion in Music” (Part XI) nicely illustrates how a debate advances. She enters into a dialogue with other contributors and defines her own position in relation to theirs. This is the familiar analytic mode. The cumulative effect of such debates is a sense of concentrated effort on carefully circumscribed ground”[ii]

There are many strands of analytic approaches so I shall highlight the basic features common to all variants, such as analysing concepts and words in a systematic and rational way including making use of logic, valuing the role of definitions and conditions, creating hypotheses and testing them, being aware of counter-examples or arguments and breaking down problems and questions into smaller, focused debates and so on. My analytic approach builds on the following excellent summary of what analytic philosophy is in ‘Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art’[iii]. It describes how ‘the idea of “analysis” is central to analytic philosophy’ although this takes many forms and varies in “the aims and methods of analysis”[iv]. They list the following general “distinctive” “Characteristics” “of the analytic methodology” as[v]:

  • “the prominent application of logic and conceptual analysis;
  • the commitment to rational methods of argument;
  • the emphasis on objectivity and truth;
  • the predilection for spare, literal prose, eschewing overly rhetorical or figurative language;
  • the felt need to define terms and offer explicit formulation of thesis;
  • the quasi-scientific dialectical method of hypothesis/counter-example/modification;
  • the tendency to tackle narrowly defined problems, often working within on-going debates.”[vi]

I agree with the above methodological approach to philosophy. Examples of this in my interpretation of Spinoza include Chapter 3 where I shall test my hypothesis by examining possible textual support for my theory and analyse the word ‘image’. In Part 2, ‘On the Role of True Worship for True Religion and Political Stability’, I make use of logic to present arguments Spinoza makes by setting it out as a deduction, which I formulated myself, from premises to conclusion to clarify my point and show the structure of his arguments. I also highlight when a claim functions as a necessary condition in Spinoza’s TTP.

Nevertheless, I would add three provisos to this. One, I don’t think that it is always correct to depreciate arguments involving subjectivity, rhetorical or figurative language. This needs to be taken on a case by case basis because some such arguments found over the course of the history of philosophy can have a lot of merit and make good points. Two, I agree with Susan James[vii] that the apparently sharp analytic-continental divide in philosophy is not always as neat or as helpful as it may seem. Three, I think the analytic approach benefits from supplementing it with textual analysis skills which helps answer the frequently asked question, nice theory but is it in the text and where and is it stated explicitly or implicitly? I think textual analysis skills especially fit together with the aspect of analytic philosophy which concerns itself with questions about which properties exist and inhere in something, be it an object, an artwork or a text, and if so, how, where and why? This has particular value in the history of philosophy where individual philosophers and their texts are examined rather than a general analysis of philosophical questions, problems, topics or paradoxes, as is usually the case in contemporary philosophy. 

Furthermore, one of the “theoretical presuppositions” of analytic philosophy which is “not universally held”, according to Lamarque and Olsen[viii], is “the belief that philosophical problems are in some sense timeless or universal, at least not merely constructs of history and culture”. I think there is an element of truth to this in the sense that Spinoza does address timeless and universal philosophical topics and questions, such as the eternal mind, substance, how to live well. A clear example of this is in the Ethics[ix] where Spinoza provides a geometric style logical argument for his ideas and conclusions. In this way, Spinoza is asking us to assent to his views through engaging our intellectual faculties to reason logically through his arguments and system of thought rather than only relying on him providing historical or cultural reasons to support them. Hence, irrespective of the era of Spinoza’s readers, we can all work through his ahistorical and non-cultural reasons and arguments whilst judging the soundness, validity and plausibility of those arguments for ourselves. Although Spinoza is responding to and drawing inspiration from debates around him as well as down the ages, I think he still attempts to make use of these debates to help him construct rational reasons and arguments which enable us to glean eternal truths about God, human nature and the universe. These now so-called analytic characteristics and presuppositions, which are nevertheless already inherent in Spinoza’s writings, mean that, I think, making use of the fundamental philosophical analytic methodology and argumentation helps to interpret him by uncovering the content, structure, reasoning and nature of his thoughts in a way that is faithful to his texts. 

However, I do not share the subsequent “widespread skepticism about the value of historically contextualized study of earlier philosophers” held by some contemporary analytic philosophers[x]. I think there can be times when “the historical development of problems”[xi] can be helpful as long as it is analysed philosophically. I make use of this historical development approach in Part 3,  ‘Was Spinoza a ‘Forerunner’ to Darwin?’, when analysing the topic of teleology by tracing debates from the pre-Socratics through to current, contemporary scientific discoveries. Here, my analytical approach is more in line with Kendall Walton in his paper 'Categories of Art’[xii] because I find his arguments more compelling than those in favour of an ahistorical approach. The salient points Walton makes about historical context, including the artist’s intentions, which I agree with are:

“It cannot be correct, I suggest, to perceive a work in categories which are totally foreign to the artist and his society…”[xiii]

“It should be emphasized that the relevant historical facts are not merely useful aids to aesthetic judgement; they do not simply provide hints concerning what might be found in the work. Rather they help to determine what aesthetic properties a work has; they, together with the work’s non-aesthetic features, make it coherent, serene, or whatever. If the origin of a work….had been different in crucial respects, the work would not have had these qualities; we would not merely have lacked a means for discovering them.”[xiv]

I think this approach is also key to understanding philosophical texts and treatises in the history of philosophy. So, cross-applying Walton’s observations[xv] to Spinoza’s writings, I argue that relevant background context shines a light on the inherent qualities and features noticeable in his texts while also acknowledging that who Spinoza was, his life experiences and his era influenced his writings and that knowing this background information aids us in detecting key features of his thought. I think his texts should also be read and interpreted within the context of his life, any known intentions he may have had and the society he lived in (both the Dutch and Jewish community). Nevertheless, I attempt to be careful not to superimpose any notions onto Spinoza which would be alien to him. For example, I do not argue in Part 3 ‘Was Spinoza a ‘Forerunner’ to Darwin?’ that Spinoza was a Darwinian because this is not possible as Darwin’s theories did not exist until two centuries later! However, this does not preclude the usefulness of comparing and contrasting Spinoza and Darwin’s ideas, arguments and theories in order to analyse the topic of teleology, assessing the philosophical strengths and weaknesses accordingly. Although it is impossible for Spinoza to have been influenced by Darwin or espouse Darwinian theories, it is an open question whether the reverse is true, especially since we know that Darwin took an interest in philosophy and the topics he is dealing with can be found in philosophy as far back as the Pre-Socratic, Empedocles. Nevertheless, Darwin also had other, non-philosophical influences so his conclusions will reflect his own independent thinking, his empirical research as well as a variety of thinkers. However, despite raising these possibilities in my arguments, I do not conclude that Darwin based his theories on Spinoza because this carries the risk of potentially superimposing notions and intentions on Darwin which he may not have had. There are other possibilities, for instance, both Spinoza and Darwin may have drawn inspiration from Empedocles and others down the ages and, therefore, there may be some similar features in their works. The purpose of comparing, contrasting and paralleling thinkers is in order to examine the properties inherent in their texts whilst, at the same time, gaining a broader perspective of how these theories are situated within the history of philosophy and the philosophy of science. In this way, each thinker is interpreted in a way which is faithful to their era and texts but not so narrowly that we lose sight of the historical context of the debates about teleology.    

This is in accordance with Susan James’s[xvi] methodology for the history of philosophy, especially where she rejects a teleological approach which results in qualities being superimposed onto a text that have been transported from another thinker or era or some other source alien to the philosopher and then ascribed to their writings. I also find Susan James’s[xvii] Contextual-Argument-Analysis interpretation (as I call it) coheres with Walton’s recommendations for good aesthetic judgement and for an historically informed analytic approach in his 'Categories of Art’[xviii] because she values and examines the origins, context and background to Spinoza’s arguments in his TTP and the society he lived in whilst also engaging in argument analysis and staying true to the properties his treatise contains. Hence, her Contextual-Argument-Analysis interpretation also gels with my Analytic-Jewish interpretation because both are in line with a Walton-style approach to philosophy and run alongside each other by drawing on different aspects of the background to Spinoza to inform philosophical analysis of his writings. Hence, I think Walton, amongst others especially in aesthetics, provides a template for analytic philosophers to remain analytic and attempt to avoid imposing bias and ideology, whether past or present, but without having to display a lack of “interest in the social, political, or ideological underpinnings” of the works they are analysing[xix]. 




[i] Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen, eds., “General Introduction,” in “Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition: An Anthology,” Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies (Wiley-Blackwell, Blackwell Publishing, 2004), 5.
[ii] Lamarque and Olsen, 5.
[iii] Lamarque and Olsen, “General Introduction.”
[iv] Lamarque and Olsen, 1.
[v] Lamarque and Olsen, 2.
[vi] Lamarque and Olsen, 2.
[vii] Susan James, “Why Should We Read Spinoza?” (Royal Institute of Philosophy, London Lecture Series 2014-15: The History of Philosophy, London, UK, 2014), https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=G5cAxJCz1Xk.
[viii] Lamarque and Olsen, “General Introduction,” 2.
[ix] Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics, trans. W.H. White and A.K. Stirling, Wordsworth Classics of World Literature (Great Britain: Wordsworth Editions, 2001).
[x] Lamarque and Olsen, “General Introduction,” 2.
[xi] Lamarque and Olsen, 2.
[xii] Kendall Walton, “Categories of Art,” in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition: An Anthology, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen, Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies (Wiley-Blackwell, Blackwell Publishing, 2004), 142–57.
[xiii] Walton, 154; 155.
[xiv] Walton, 145.
[xv] Walton, 142–57.
[xvi] James, “Why Should We Read Spinoza?”
[xvii] Susan James, Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics, The Theologico-Political Treatise (Oxford University Press, 2014).
[xviii] Walton, “Categories of Art,” 142–57.
[xix] Lamarque and Olsen, “General Introduction,” 2.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.