Tuesday 9 January 2018

Spinoza vol 1 ebook Chapter 2: The Jewish Orthodox Interpretation within My Analytic-Jewish Interpretation



In Spinoza’s Apology to his synagogue that he wrote in response to his excommunication, Spinoza is believed to have adamantly claimed that his ideas are, contrary to how he is perceived, in line with Orthodox Judaism[i]. Scruton goes as far as to state that, in this Apology, it is believed that Spinoza "defended his views as orthodox”[ii]. It seems that Spinoza’s own explanation for his excommunication is “merely” that the rabbis over-reacted to the fact that he “had neglected ceremonial observances”[iii]. Although “no copies” of this Apology are now available to analyse, Scruton[iv] claims that “its contents were probably later included in the Theologico-Political Treatise” (TTP), which is why, in this chapter, I wish to take a closer look at this text. 

Given this, I would like to re-examine Spinoza in light of this claim of Spinoza’s that he remained an orthodox Jew at heart with Orthodox Jewish views, even after his excommunication. Although this is a statement coming from Spinoza himself, as far as I am aware, philosophical scholarship and research has not yet examined to what extent one can find orthodox Jewish thought at work throughout Spinoza’s texts, especially since Nadler[v] states that the relationship between Jewish thought and Spinoza “is too often neglected in philosophical scholarship on Spinoza”. Nadler[vi] further adds “there is still more work to be done on the broader Jewish philosophical background of the TTP”. Moreover, Nadler[vii] specifies that, “in the post-Wolfson period, the more intricate philosophical task of identifying Jewish elements in Spinoza’s thought, and doing so not impressionistically but with solid comparative analyses and arguments” is lacking. I agree with Nadler and wish to take on this approach, however, I would like to press this connection further and more consistently than him. This is partly because I disagree with Nadler’s[viii] claim that Spinoza “seems not to have had any residual sense of Jewish identity. In his writings, he goes out of his way to distance himself from Judaism, and always refers to the Jews in the third person as “them”. Nor does he exhibit any fundamental sympathy with Jewish history or culture; indeed, he seems to harbor a degree of hostility to the Jewish people”. If I understand Nadler[ix] correctly, he holds in tension that Judaism is vital to understanding Spinoza’s thought processes yet, at the same time, wishing to claim that Spinoza “had great contempt for Judaism”. I find this a contradictory approach which doesn’t sit well and is possibly mistaken. Hence, one of the aspects of Spinoza I would like to explore is the possibility of a fresh interpretation of Spinoza by interpreting him as a religious Orthodox Jewish philosopher in light of the Jewish Orthodoxy that was available to, and an influence on him, in his lifetime. I also think it is informative to take account of Judaism when examining Spinoza’s works, irrespective of one’s desired overall account.

Susan James[x] states that she “aims to do something different” by claiming that “Works of philosophy are best understood as contributions to ongoing conversations or debates”. In this way, rather than situate her interpretative approach within one of the pre-existing categories she lists, for instance a Cartesian or Jewish interpretation, she carves out her own niche by creating a new branch of interpretative approach which I call the Contextual-Argument-Analysis interpretation. I agree with her that philosophical texts should be seen in the context of the philosophical debates surrounding them. Further to this, I think that this task need not be done separately from considering prior and ongoing debates in Judaism. I suspect that one can also appreciate Spinoza’s premises via Judaism since this approach renders Spinoza consistent within his own premises and conclusions and consistent between his ideas and Judaism. However, given that Susan James[xi] specifically states she is not doing a Jewish interpretation, the fact that she does not tend to address Jewish issues in her interpretation is neither surprising nor does it negatively impact on her approach. Indeed, I wish to build on her Contextual-Argument-Analysis and non-teleological approach and, like her, try to do something different but within the Jewish interpretation by providing an Orthodox Jewish insight into Spinoza and his works and by drawing on the overall methodologies in analytic philosophy. This fulfils a research need because Nadler[xii] highlights that analytic philosophy tends to concentrate on Descartes’ influence on Spinoza rather than any Jewish influences on him. I acknowledge there were many other influences on Spinoza apart from Judaism, such as Descartes, Hobbes, Grotius, and friends he corresponded with and met as well as the Dutch society he lived in[xiii]. Susan James[xiv] has achieved such a thorough examination of the Dutch context and arguments that Spinoza is responding to that I shall refer readers to her analysis of this rather than attempt to cover this aspect in great depth myself.

Spinoza’s “formative” education involved the study of Judaism and Jewish thought, including Maimonides, Kabbalah and the Talmud[xv]. Indeed, he was steeped in Judaism from his childhood years at the “elementary school of the united Talmud Torah congregation” through to and including possibly “adult studies in the Keter Torah yeshiva run by the congregation’s chief rabbi, the Ashkenazic import Saul Levi Mortera”[xvi]. This suggests to me that the Talmud (writings on Jewish oral law and rabbinic commentaries on it) and Torah (containing the first five books of Moses often with rabbinic commentaries) must have made a hugely lasting impression on Spinoza. Indeed, this is further supported by the fact that Spinoza was writing a Hebrew grammar book alongside writing his Ethics and Political Treatise[xvii] which would indicate to me that Spinoza continued both his sense of Jewish identity and his interest in Jewish language, thought, the Jewish community and religious beliefs because Hebrew is seen as a holy language for Jews. Not only is it the language of Jewish prayer but Hebrew letters and words also have many layers of meaning and possible interpretations. This perhaps can be seen when Spinoza expresses his strong views in his TTP about how to read, translate and interpret scripture linguistically and how to deal with linguistically obscure passages in order to stay theologically accurate and rigorous. This forms part of his argument for keeping theology and philosophy distinct and is his main objection to Maimonides’s methodology of using philosophy to fill in the gaps in our scriptural understanding[xviii]. Although both theology and philosophy can grasp true religion, their methodology must be separate and so remain only within the scope and methods and language of each discipline[xix]. By demarcating philosophy and theology as distinct disciplines which have and give their own style of reasons, arguments and justifications, which are of equal value in themselves, Spinoza also attempts to solve the common problem of philosophers and theologians clashing with each other and it causing social and religious tensions[xx]. In this way, Spinoza is also arguing against what Susan James[xxi] calls the teleological approach in that one must not superimpose something alien to one thing onto another. In the TTP, this amounts to not superimposing philosophy onto theology and vice versa, as well as not superimposing the properties, ideologies, bias or a different era, thinker or culture onto a text. In this way, Spinoza advocates the methodology of focusing on the properties inherent in the text and discipline to thereby fulfil the aim of staying accurate and faithful to the text. Hence, I think that the Orthodox Jewish views expressed in Spinoza’s premises have been somewhat under-researched and so my focus will be on that aspect, in the hope that this gives one a clearer understanding of Spinoza’s philosophical arguments.

I suggest an interpretation of Spinoza that simultaneously holds two things in tension. On the one hand, Spinoza was an unique, philosophical genius that could “ab initio” deduce truths from premises that are “unpolluted by received ideas”[xxii]. This is important because “Spinoza would have condemned the practice (known nowadays as the ‘history of ideas’) whereby a study of the ancestry of ideas takes precedence over an enquiry into their truth and meaning”[xxiii]. Yet, on the other hand, Spinoza utilized the unusual education he received in mainstream and Jewish philosophy as well as in Judaism to enhance and deepen his ideas and arguments. I think one should bear in mind that part of this unusual education was Spinoza’s “early teachers” which included the “orthodox senior rabbi of Amsterdam, Rabbi Saul Morteira, and the liberal Rabbi Manasseh ben Israel, a man of wide learning and secular interests, friend of Vossius, Grotius, and Rembrandt”[xxiv]. In this way, Rabbi Manasseh ben Israel could have been a possible role model for Spinoza because Manasseh could hold in tension being an orthodox Jew, a rabbi, and yet, at the same time, having liberal attitudes and secular interests. Rabbi Manasseh ben Israel wrote books in Latin which were also aimed at non-Jewish readers even though they contained Jewish thought, he had connections with a range of scholars including Christians such as Anna Maria de Schurman, and was familiar enough with Christian, Ancient Greek and Latin works to include them in his own writings[xxv]. So, I think it would be natural for Spinoza to think he could do likewise and gain the same wider readership that Rabbi Manasseh enjoyed without compromising his Orthodox Judaism or being excommunicated. Hence, I would argue that, just because Spinoza has apparently progressive ideas in his writings, he may not have seen this as being in opposition to Orthodox Judaism or a sign that he had rejected Judaism or become an atheist. Spinoza may have, at times, disagreed with some rabbinic approaches but one must also remember that Spinoza does not disagree with every rabbi, as can be seen when he agrees with and cites Rabbi Abraham Ibn Ezra on Mosaic authorship[xxvi]. Although Ibn Ezra was a somewhat controversial figure, he is nevertheless seen as a key thinker and one who is very knowledgeable about Judaism, a deeply spiritual man who even engaged in discussions with the grandson of Rashi[xxvii]. Ironically, this now deeply revered rabbi, Abraham Ibn Ezra, was also excommunicated which just goes to show that excommunication from a synagogue means nothing. It happens to the best of them. Spinoza is in good company. Interestingly, it was while Rabbi Manasseh ben Israel was in London, England (which was under Oliver Cromwell at the time) to work for the readmission of the Jews into England, that Spinoza was excommunicated following a tribunal headed by Rabbi Morteira in 1656. Was there rivalry between the two rabbis? Was it a rivalry between Ashkenazi and Sephardi Jews?

Moreover, debating is par for the course in Judaism where differing rabbinic opinions are argued about and even disagreed with since no-one can agree with every rabbinic thought uttered because there is so much of it and it expresses very diverse opinions and approaches. As Rabbi Susan Grossman describes it:

“The Talmud is full of such debates: different opinions are tried, compared and tested. Often a successful conclusion means finding how the opinions of two or more rabbis can be internally consistent (and therefore legitimate) even if they represent diametrically opposite opinions. The model of Talmudic study has not only honed our ability to think clearly but has also created a Jewish culture open to the difference of opinions.”[xxviii]

Rabbi Dr. Weinreb similarly points out:

“We all nod our heads in agreement when we hear the phrase, “Two Jews, three opinions.””[xxix]

So I think this style of Spinoza’s is not symptomatic of a dismissal of Judaism either but is actually characteristic of the Jewish approach to thinking independently, open-mindedly and being able to hold two or more divergent opinions in tension and not being over-concerned with tradition. As Rabbi Weinreb continues:

“….it is apparent that our sages do not categorically oppose dispute, debate, and argument. Rather, everything depends upon the motive. …………

They particularly appreciated disputes which were motivated by the search for truth. Hence, hardly a page in the thousands of pages of the Talmud does not record strong differences of opinion between the rabbis. …………

Students of Torah must not only study the content of these ancient disputes. They must also learn to re-create the atmosphere which prevailed among the disputants, an atmosphere of civility and mutual respect and a willingness to concede one’s original position in order to achieve the truth.”[xxx]

On this picture given by Rabbis Susan Grossman and Tzvi Weinreb, Spinoza fits in well with Jewish culture throughout the ages, always questioning and thinking for himself in his search for truth. Therefore, I find Spinoza’s claim that he remained Orthodox in his views all the more compelling given that he was a principled man who seems to have never wished to state anything contrary to his genuine beliefs or compromise his philosophical stances throughout his life but rather favoured stating the truth, even if just on principle. For instance, he declined the University post offered to him by Heidelberg University to avoid any pressure to compromise his philosophical principles[xxxi].

So, I think that one can plausibly believe Spinoza that he really did feel he remained Orthodox in his outlook even after his excommunication and would not have simply claimed to be so just for personal gain or to placate the synagogue authorities. 



[i] Scruton, Spinoza, 9.
[ii] Scruton, 9.
[iii] Scruton, 9.
[iv] Scruton, 9.
[v] Nadler, Spinoza’s Heresy: Immortality and the Jewish Mind, xi.
[vi] Nadler, “The Jewish Spinoza,” 502.
[vii] Nadler, 496.
[viii] Nadler, 492.
[ix] Nadler, 492.
[x] James, Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics, The Theologico-Political Treatise, 3–4.
[xi] James, Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics, The Theologico-Political Treatise.
[xii] Nadler, “The Jewish Spinoza,” 496.
[xiii] Scruton, Spinoza, 20.; Nadler, Spinoza’s Heresy: Immortality and the Jewish Mind.; James, Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics, The Theologico-Political Treatise.
[xiv] James, Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics, The Theologico-Political Treatise.
[xv] Scruton, Spinoza, 20.
[xvi] Nadler, “The Jewish Spinoza,” 491–92.
[xvii] Scruton, Spinoza, 12.
[xviii] Benedict de Spinoza, A Theologico-Political Treatise and A Political Treatise, trans. R. H. M. Elwes, Dover Philosophical Classics (Mineola, New York, USA: Dover Publications Inc, 2004), VII, 115.
[xix] Spinoza, TTP Trans. Elwes.
[xx] Spinoza.
[xxi] James, “Why Should We Read Spinoza?”
[xxii] Scruton, Spinoza, 19–20.
[xxiii] Scruton, 21.
[xxiv] Scruton, 6.
[xxv] Joseph Jacobs, “Manasseh Ben Israel,” Jewish Encyclopedia, n.d., http://www.jewishencyclopedia.com/articles/10345-manasseh-ben-israel.
[xxvi] Spinoza, TTP Trans. Elwes, X, 146.
[xxvii] Anon., “Abraham Ibn Ezra,” Jewish Virtual Library, n.d., https://www.jewishvirtuallibrary.org/abraham-ibn-ezra. Rashi was a great, seminal commentator on the Talmud and the Tanach (the Hebrew Bible, also known as the Old Testament) whom everyone studies at every level of Jewish education.

[xxviii] Rabbi Susan Grossman, “Two Jews Three Opinions,” beliefnet.com, accessed October 30, 2017, http://www.beliefnet.com/columnists/virtualtalmud/2007/05/two-jews-three-opinions.html.
[xxix] Rabbi Dr. Tzvi Hersh Weinreb, “Rabbi Weinreb’s Parsha Column, Korach: ‘Two Jews Three Opinions,’” ou.org (Orthodox Union), accessed October 30, 2017, https://www.ou.org/torah/parsha/rabbi-weinreb-on-parsha/rabbi-weinrebs-parsha-column-korach-two-jews-three-opinions/.
[xxx] Weinreb.
[xxxi] Scruton, Spinoza, 13–14.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.